The Homunculus Fallacy and its Inverse

Imagine a little girl asking her father how a car works. “What makes it go?” she asks him. He tells her that inside the car, there is a smaller car driving on a treadmill, which is connected to the wheels of the bigger car. As the little car drives on the treadmill, the big car drives on the road.

Of course, he is just teasing her with an absurd explanation. Cars don’t have little cars inside them, but even if they did, this “explanation” isn’t really an explanation. To explain what makes the big car go, he would now have to explain what makes the little car go. The explanation presupposes what it is supposed to explain: cars that go.

But it has the form of an explanation, and it might confuse the little girl into believing that her question has been answered.

A more typical example of the homunculus fallacy is the use of a “little man in the head” to explain aspects of consciousness. For example, someone might “explain” vision as “the mind’s eye is looking at a screen in the brain”. This is not an explanation of vision, because it presupposes vision. Even if it described some brain process metaphorically, it would not explain vision. We would now have to explain how the “mind’s eye” can “see”.

An explanation of vision should be in terms of lower-level mental processes that are mechanistic and do not presuppose vision. An explanation of how a car moves should involve objects and processes (pistons, gears, combustion, etc.) that are neither cars nor driving.

Explanations typically describe hidden mechanisms and invoke general principles that define how those mechanisms work. For example, we can explain the movements of the planets by a hidden mechanism (gravity) that operates by general principles (Newton’s laws of motion and gravitational attraction). This explanation not only allows us to predict the movements of the planets, it also relates them to many other things, such as an apple falling from a tree. It shows how something specific (planetary motion) is an instance of something very general (motion and gravity). Newton’s theory of motion and gravity has explanatory power, because it can be used to generate such explanations for many things. It reduces complexity by describing and predicting many things with a small number of abstract concepts.

Of course, we could always ask “Why does the world work that way?”. We could seek an explanation for Newton’s theory. We could try to reduce it, and other theories, to an even more general theory. But we would always be left with some theory, and we could always ask for a deeper explanation.

The homunculus fallacy is a pseudo-explanation: an explanation that does not explain, because it does not reduce what it tries to explain to a more abstract level of description. Instead, it posits a hidden mechanism at the same level of description. This hidden mechanism is what it supposedly explains. (The little car inside the big car, for example.) In most cases, this is done through a metaphor, and the person committing the fallacy is not aware of their error. They may find it hard to recognize the error, even if it is pointed out, because the metaphor has become entrenched in their way of viewing things.

It is very common to think of human motivation and action as pursuing pleasure and avoiding pain. In this view, we want pleasure and we don’t want pain, so we act to pursue pleasure and avoid pain. This view is very intuitive. However, it is based on a homunculus metaphor, and it contains a homunculus fallacy.

Pursuit and avoidance are behaviors. The concepts of pursuit and avoidance presuppose motivation and action. Behavior is what a theory of human motivation and action is supposed to explain. So, we cannot explain human motivation and action with the concepts of pursuit and avoidance. The use of “pursuit” and “avoidance” to describe mental processes is a homunculus metaphor. This metaphor is misleading, because it presupposes motivation and action.

We can think of the motivation system as a little man in the head who chases pleasure on a treadmill, and runs away from pain, but this metaphor gets us nowhere. Even if it described some mental process, we would now have to explain why the little man wants pleasure, and why he doesn’t want pain. We would have to explain his motivations.

To explain human motivation and action, we must describe a mechanism that does not have the properties (motivation and action) that we want to explain, and that mechanism should operate by more general principles.

Vision cannot be explained in terms of vision. Motivation cannot be explained in terms of motivation. Consciousness cannot be explained in terms of consciousness.

The homunculus fallacy “explains” a system by positing a part of the system that has the properties of the whole system. It conceptually presupposes what it claims to explain. It is conceptual question-begging.

There is an inverse of the homunculus fallacy. The inverse homunculus fallacy “explains” a system by positing that it is a part of a bigger system that has the properties of the smaller system. It also presupposes what it claims to explain, but by projecting a part onto the whole, rather than the whole onto a part.

The classic, absurd example of the inverse homunculus fallacy is the “world-turtle”: the theory that the world sits on the back of a giant turtle.

See World Turtle on Wikipedia.

We can imagine how this pseudo-explanation arose. A little girl asks her father “What holds the world up?”.

This is a perfectly reasonable question for a little child or an Indian peasant in 500 AD. In ordinary life, objects fall unless they are held up by something, or actively kept up by some process, such as a bird flapping its wings. So, our ordinary intuition is that things fall. Today, most people know that the Earth is a ball in space, and that up and down are not absolute directions, but are relative to the center of the Earth. Without this modern knowledge, it is quite natural to think of the Earth as unmoving, and up and down as absolute directions. It is also quite natural to wonder what lies below.

The father of the little girl tells her “The world is sitting a turtle’s back”.

Of course, this explains nothing. A turtle is an object that exists on the Earth. Turtles are normally held up by the ground or by water when they are swimming. They have something underneath them. They need air, water and food. The idea of a turtle presupposes the Earth as a whole. Our ordinary assumptions about how the world works are hidden inside the concept of a turtle. But those ordinary assumptions are what we are trying to explain.

The little girl might ask “What holds the turtle up?”. The philosophical joke-answer is that it is turtles all the way down. The father could say that the turtle is standing on another turtle. Or he might say that the turtle is standing on the surface of a bigger world. Either way, the “explanation” does not explain.

A turtle-believer might insist that the turtle theory does explain things. For example, it explains earthquakes: those are caused by the turtle moving. But then why aren’t earthquakes always happening? Why do they happen in specific places? What are volcanoes caused by? Why aren’t there periodic floods when the turtle goes for a swim? And so on. Just because a theory is consistent with some (cherry-picked) data, it doesn’t follow that the theory has explanatory power. It must reduce the complexity of the data to have explanatory power.

God is another example of the inverse homunculus fallacy. Supposedly, the concept of God explains various things, such as the existence of the Earth, the existence of life, human nature, rationality, etc. But the concept of God presupposes those things. God is a metaphorical person. He has the properties of a human being. He exists. He is alive. He has desires. He thinks and acts.

The Christian notion of God is analogous to the world-turtle. It tries to explain the universe in terms of something that exists within the universe: a person. Of course, the imaginary person of God is BIG in various ways, just as the world-turtle is big. God doesn’t just think and act. He is omniscient and omnipotent!!

One could use the same trick with the world-turtle, by claiming that the turtle is infinitely big. Then there would be nothing underneath the turtle. It would be “turtle all the way down” instead of “turtles all the way down”. Of course, it still wouldn’t explain anything.

Like turtles, human beings exist on the Earth, and our properties are tied to our way of existence. Mental operations, such as thought, desire and action, are ways of solving the problems of living beings. They are adaptations. It makes no sense to extend them to infinity, or attribute them to a universal being.

If God is omnipotent, then there is no distinction between his will and reality. But will is the desire to change reality. Omnipotence is an absurd notion, or it is just a confusing way to say “causality”. Likewise for omniscience. If God is omniscient, then there is no distinction between his knowledge and reality. But knowledge is limited information about reality, not reality itself. Just as “up” and “down” are only meaningful on the Earth (or some other large body), “knowledge” and “will” are only meaningful for limited beings, such as us.

For more about the conceptual incoherence of the God concept, see To EyesWideOpen.

If we eliminate the human properties of God, exchanging “will” for “causality” and “knowledge” for “existence”, then we have exchanged “God” for “reality”. Any apparent explanatory power of the God-concept comes from conceptual question-begging, through the metaphor of God as a human being.

The cosmological arguments for God involve the inverse homunculus fallacy. They insist that we must posit God to explain reality, but their notion of God presupposes the properties that are “explained”. Like the world-turtle, the concept of God smuggles in ordinary assumptions about reality.

“All is mind” is a more modern, sophisticated version of the world-turtle. Supposedly, the human mind is explained by claiming that everything is mind. This uses the human mind as a metaphor for the whole of reality. Of course, the metaphor smuggles in all the properties of the human mind. The great virtue of this “metaphysical theory” is that it “explains” the human mind. But of course, it does no such thing. It simply shifts the problem of explanation to reality as a whole, just as the world-turtle shifts the problem of what holds the world up to what holds the turtle up.

“The universe is a computer (program)” is another example of the inverse homunculus fallacy. It applies the metaphor of a computer to the universe as a whole. But of course, a computer is something that exists within the universe. It is a mechanism that operates according to physical laws. So, nothing is explained by positing that the universe is a computer or a computer program.

Subtler versions of these fallacies are involved in certain scientific theories and problems. For example, the “selfish gene” concept is a homunculus metaphor. (See Debunking the Selfish Gene.)

We can’t avoid using metaphors, and metaphors will normally be at the ordinary level of description. We often project ordinary things “upward” or “downward” to explain bigger or smaller things. Sometimes, this creates a circular explanation.

Many people (and not just little girls) have been tricked by these fallacies.

Comments

  1. I have nothing to say on the article other than that I totally agree. I just want to say that your way of thinking and writing is really inspiring and I have so much fun reading through your thoughts

    ReplyDelete
  2. I am curious to know if you have heard of a guy named Mario Alejandro Montano. If you have, what are your thoughts concerning him and his ideas?

    By the way, this blog is quite insightful. I have always known some of the homunculus fallacy examples that you mentioned, but I never gave much thought to them. Thank you for sharing!

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. If he was Kill(ss)ing Asuka then I have seen one or two of his videos. Someone posted his channel in my discord server a few years ago. It seems that he went psychotic and committed suicide. Sad.

      I haven't really listened to his videos, so I don't know what his ideas are. Looking at his channel, he seems to have been a quantum theory mystic. So, my guess is that his ideas are just mystical speculation. People like to speculate about the multiverse or quantum immortality, but those concepts have no explanatory power.

      Glad you find the blog interesting. Thanks for your comment.

      Delete
    2. Thank you for the reply! The sole reason I asked the question in the first place is that I have lately been concerned with subjective experience. Questions like what dictates why I am in this body and not another, and vice versa, are what I am ruminating on. I am aware that my body is merely the product of reproduction and evolution and that my personality and mentality are shaped by both nature and nurture. However, it does not acknowledge why I experience this particular body in this particular time and universe. Some may say I simply am, which seems intuitively correct, but is not a satisfactory response to me. I am curious to know what your thoughts are on this matter.

      Delete
    3. Some questions don't have answers. For example, you can ask "Why does the universe exist?", but you can't answer it, because any causal explanation is within the universe. You could claim that the universe exists within a bigger universe, or within a multiverse, but that's like saying the world is on a turtle's back. You would then have to ask why the multiverse exists (what holds up the turtle?).

      Certain mysteries are intrinsic to subjectivity. You can always wonder why you are you and not somebody else -- but if you were anybody else you could ask the same question. Subjectivity will always have some perspective, and the subject can always ask "Why this perspective?", but there is no way to answer that question.

      When people pretend to answer these questions, they are engaging in mystical speculation. Or they could be psychotic, as Kill(ss)ing Asuka was. Psychotics often develop the delusion that they are God: a universal perspective, rather than just a perspective.

      But that doesn't mean such questions are pointless. They are worth asking. It's part of a process of becoming philosophically aware. Instead of a magical turtle (or quantum theory, or God), there is the abyss.

      Delete
    4. It is rather unfortunate that there are some questions that will never be answered. Perhaps I have been staring at the abyss for too long. I cannot help but ask questions that I mostly know I will never have the answers to. Before I end this conversation, I would like to know if you have ever experienced existential dread or depression before, and if so, do you have any advice on how someone can cope with it effectively? I have tried many methods to "treat" it, primarily by looking deeper into and understanding philosophical concepts and arguments, but they only provide a transient sense of certainty and comfort. The dread never goes away. The same can be applied to most of my activities, such as socializing and learning; they all seem like distractions from the dread (or at least satisfying my biological needs, or a combination of both), yet I still feel empty inside, sometimes even alienated from my peers. Anyway, I want to thank you for your time and expertise! It was nice having this conversation.

      Delete
    5. Yeah, I went through a period of depression when I was young, after I discovered that there is no ultimate foundation for belief. Nihilism is something that you have to go through before you can have a rational worldview. You have to let go of the idea that you have a foundation, and accept your ultimate authority/responsibility for your beliefs and actions. There is no foundation, but you have a nature. I talked about that in Lucifer's Question:

      https://youtu.be/am1UbxmQX10

      If you want to talk more about it, discord is the best place

      https://discord.gg/zfMtWK2

      Delete

Post a Comment